And the sky, the light,
the trees, the whole of Nature would be, as always, in league with them: Daniel was a man of evil will. (136)
This
curious line describes Daniel, the only homosexual character in The Age of Reason, and his perception of
himself. It is an unflattering image imbued with self-loathing, indicative of a
mind that views its perceiver as a social outcast and a victim of universal
oppression. It is interesting to note that Daniel’s homosexuality is hidden
from the public, and that there is no indication that he has been openly
discriminated against – and yet, what we have here is a young man in his prime,
possessor of a “dark, handsome, blue-jowled visage,” whom Marcelle ironically
calls “her dear archangel” (82), grappling with a self-hatred so powerful that
every thought crossing his mind is associated with destruction and death.
Our
first proper introduction to him takes place in Chapter 7, and it is here that
we find Daniel shaving “naked to the waist,” thinking “it wouldn’t be a bad
joke to deface the head they all admired” (82). Daniel is aware that women (and
most likely men as well) are attracted to him because of his uncommonly good
looks; but this knowledge leaves him cold. He does not deface himself on this
occasion (nor on subsequent similar occasions), reasoning that he likes to be goodlooking.
The
chapter then continues with Daniel picking up his three pet cats and stuffing
them into a basket (the act is described in cringing detail). What he intends
to do is to drown the cats in the Seine. On his way there he has “a vision that
penetrated everything, and saw to the very end of the world”:
Daniel
noticed that he was a few steps in advance of his body – yonder, at the level
of the gas-jet, and that he was watching his own progress, hobbling a little
under his burden … he saw himself come, he was no more than a disembodied
vision. (87)
These
lines that detail an out-of-body experience before the committing of an extreme
act parallel the later passage where Mathieu also has a similar experience
while drinking with his friends in the Sumatra. It is a unique fleeting moment,
an unstable vision that only presents itself at the point when someone has
decided to “take action.” In Daniel’s case, it is the drowning of what “I love
most in the world,” because he “hasn’t the courage to kill himself” (90). He
thinks of Mathieu then, priding himself on being the one who is “free,” the one
who dares to do what is necessary to change. But Daniel does not go through
with the act, and he returns to his apartment with the cats in the basket only
to run into Mathieu. “He was glad to be able to hate another person,” the
narrator tells us when Daniel realises Mathieu has come to see him. Mathieu has
come to borrow the money he needs for Marcelle’s abortion, but Daniel makes him
believe that he does not have the money. After Mathieu leaves, Daniel goes up
to the mirror and inspects his “dark and comely countenance,” thinking that “it
would be worth a packet if he (Mathieu) were forced to marry Marcelle” (97).
This
may come across as sheer vindictiveness, but if the reader interprets the
entire episode in the light of Sartre’s coinage of “bad faith” (mauvaise foi – a term referring to the
conflict between oppressive, deadening conformity and the “authentic state of
being”), Daniel’s decision not to lend Mathieu the money and his desire to see
him forced into marriage can be seen as a counter-reaction to his own failure
to liberate himself from his own “bad faith.”
Daniel
is as much a victim of “bad faith” as Mathieu; indecision and self-hatred keep
him deeply rooted in abjection. The most apparent example can be found in
Chapter 9, where Daniel impulsively decides to go to the fair, and while there
he chances upon a young man he is attracted to (“he ached to put his hand on
the young man’s arm”), but is spared the “humiliation” of having to seduce the
young man when an older “handsome gentleman” comes into the picture. Daniel
feels at that point he is “delivered,” and is pleased with himself because “he
had resisted” (129).
Daniel
views the older seducer disapprovingly, but his view of the young man who gives
in to the older man’s advances is even harsher:
Daniel
looked disgustedly at his plump hips, his broad bucolic cheeks, grey and
already begrimed with an incipient beard. ‘Female flesh,’ he thought, ‘as lush
as dough.’ The gentleman would take him home, give him a bath, soap him, and
perhaps scent him. At this thought, Daniel’s rage revived. ‘Swine,’ he
murmured. (130)
The
language here betrays an undeniable sense of envy. Daniel despises the older
man and the young man and judges them for their “immoral” transaction for only
one reason: he himself would have liked to take the older gentleman’s place.
When he eventually leaves the fair by himself, alone and lonely, he knows he
has failed once again to take action, concluding with these dejected words:
“Living the life I do, I can always expect to break up pretty soon” (136).
Daniel
is confronted with change later on, in Chapter 16, when he succumbs to his
same-sex desire and has a sexual encounter with Ralph. The incident itself,
placed in the claustrophobic setting of Ralph’s attic room, spans only a little
more than four pages. The intimacy between the two men is coloured with violent
language, projected through Daniel’s point of view. Here we again find Daniel
standing in front of a mirror dressing up (a recurring image). While doing so,
he is also scrutinising Ralph in the mirror: “He could see Ralph’s haggard,
harsh profile, and his hands began to tremble: he longed to squeeze that thin
neck with its protuberant Adam’s apple, and feel it crack beneath his finger”
(261). He also projects his own murderous rage onto Ralph: “He’s looking
positively murderous … he’s hurt in his little masculine pride, he hates me” (261, italics mine).
Their
conversation also veers towards acts of violence, with Ralph recounting how he
knocked out a man once. Upon hearing this, Daniel is “seized by an access of
rage,” and longs to “knock him down” (263). When he leaves Ralph behind, his
first thought is to “wash myself from head to foot” (265), a clear indication
that he is disgusted with the whole experience. Despite his endeavour to break
out of his “bad faith,” the move has not been successful. It is later proved to
be counter-productive, ballooning his already all-consuming self-loathing, and
leading him to contemplate self-mutilation (see Part 1 for Mathieu’s
self-mutilating act).
Daniel
is compelled to “dead the beast, dead the poison” (266), the “beast” and the
“poison” being his homosexual essence. Back in his own apartment, his attention
is claimed by a gleaming razor. He seriously considers using the razor on
himself (though Sartre’s language is ambiguous at this point, we find out later
that he had intended to castrate himself). He is acutely conscious of being
alone in the process: “Nothing impels him to decide, nothing stops him from
doing so: he alone must decide” (267). This line corresponds with the Sartrean
notion that in the existentialist universe we have no-one but ourselves to
answer to.
What
follows next is perhaps to be expected: Daniel gets cold feet and does not go
through with the gruesome act. He shame-facedly admits to himself that “when he
picked up the razor, he had not deceived himself for one second” (270). The
admittance tells the reader that Daniel, though teemed with self-destructive
thoughts, will never have the courage to harm himself. He is, however, different
from all the other characters in the novel – Mathieu, Ivich, Boris, Lola –
because he is conscious of his failure to
dispel his “bad faith.” The others, one could venture to say, are only
marginally aware of being slaves to “bad faith” and do not even make an effort
to break free. In other words, being an “outcast” has heightened his
self-consciousness.
The
next time we meet Daniel is in the final chapter, where he announces to Mathieu
that he will be marrying Marcelle to save her from ruin, and makes his
confession. When asked why he would do such a thing, he says he is not doing it
out of philanthropy or out of love. He is merely doing it to keep Marcelle from
being unhappy. None of Daniel’s reasons for marrying Marcelle are completely
convincing, but when Mathieu says that Daniel’s intention has made him “more
disgusted with [himself],” Daniel replies: “Yes … I suppose you must be feeling
pretty rotten” (296). His words suggest that his intention to marry Marcelle
has more to do with Mathieu than with Marcelle’s happiness. It becomes all the
more obvious when Mathieu asks him if it would not be better if he were “to
accept the fact (of his being homosexual).” Daniel’s response to this is one of
annoyance:
You
can say that to me, when you have accepted the fact that you’re a swine … No,
homosexuals who boast of it or proclaim it, or merely acquiesce … are dead men.
Their very sense of shame has killed them. I don’t want to die that sort of
death. (297)
Daniel’s
lines are full of ironic contradictions. They show that his intention is to
coerce Mathieu into accepting responsibility for what he has done, to spur him
to action; but at the same time, they reveal that his motive is based on a
steely denial of his homosexual self. He has broken away from his “bad faith”
for all the wrong reasons.
Mathieu,
however, does not see this. He is in awe of Daniel’s gumption and is overcome
with envy: “‘It’s true,’ thought Mathieu: ‘he went right through with it, this
time … he is free’ … And the horror with which Daniel inspired him was suddenly
combined with envy” (298). Here is where the novel’s irony reaches its peak:
Daniel the homosexual denies his own sexuality and makes an inappropriate
choice that Mathieu interprets as an “act of freedom.” The novel ends with
Mathieu coming to terms with all the failures in his life. Before the novel
comes to a close, he casually repeats to himself: “It’s true, it’s absolutely
true: I have attained the age of reason” (299). This is miles from the truth.
Mathieu, at this point, still has not
shown any inclination to move beyond what he is accustomed to.
It
is an opaque ending that will frustrate a lot of readers. Is Sartre saying that
human beings are incapable of eliminating “bad faith,” even when they are
conscious of being its prisoners? And if they do attempt to, is it not often a
case of leaping from the frying pan into the roaring fire, as in Daniel’s case?
True to the Sartrean enigma, no cookie-cutter answers are to be found in this
first volume of Roads to Freedom.
Sartre,
Jean-Paul. The Age of Reason. London:
Penguin Books, 2001 Penguin Classics ed.
Comments
Post a Comment
Comments are always appreciated! Do feel free to leave them or start a discussion.